Viewpoint

Seeking Stability in a Relativistic Fluid

    Gabriel Denicol
    • Department of Physics, Fluminense Federal University, Niterói, Brazil
Physics 15, 149
A fluid dynamics theory that violates causality would always generate paradoxical instabilities—a result that could guide the search for a theory for relativistic fluids.
L. Gavassino [1]; adapted by APS/Alan Stonebraker
Figure 1: In Alice’s reference frame (left), a perturbation to a fluid moves superluminally from left to right. Its intensity (orange) decreases with time as a result of dissipation. For Bob (right), who is in motion relative to Alice, the perturbation moves from right to left, and its intensity grows with time. For both Bob and Alice, the superluminal perturbation falls outside of the light cone (blue dashed lines) and violates causality. This simple point-of-view analysis leads to a stability criterion for any relativistic-fluid-dynamical theory: a theory that is stable and causal in one reference frame is stable in all reference frames.

The theory of fluid dynamics has been successful in many areas of fundamental and applied sciences, describing fluids from dilute gases, such as air, to liquids, such as water. For most nonrelativistic fluids, the theory takes the form of the celebrated Navier-Stokes equation. However, fundamental problems arise when extending these equations to relativistic fluids. Such extensions typically imply paradoxes—for instance, thermodynamic states of the systems can appear stable or unstable to observers in different frames of reference. These problems hinder the description of the dynamics of important fluid systems, such as neutron-rich matter in neutron star mergers or the quark-gluon plasma produced in heavy-ion collisions. Now Lorenzo Gavassino of the Polish Academy of Sciences establishes a simple criterion to determine whether a given relativistic-fluid-dynamical theory is associated with paradoxical instabilities [1]: if a theory violates causality, it will also generate such instabilities. The result will provide important guidance in the search for a viable theory for relativistic fluids.

In the past two decades, many fluid-dynamical theories have been developed to address the nonphysical aspects of extensions of the Navier-Stokes theory [27]. The most famous, derived by Israel and Stewart, is applied extensively in nuclear physics [6]. All these efforts were based on the premise that a consistent theory of relativistic fluid dynamics must be causal in order to be stable. This assumption was suggested by many stability analyses and implied that causality and stability are intimately related: if a theory allows for signals propagating faster than the speed of light—in other words, if it violates causality—the analyses typically found observer-dependent instabilities. For example, perturbing a viscous fluid (in equilibrium) at rest leads to stable, exponentially decaying modes—the typical behavior expected for a dissipative fluid. But perturbing the same fluid in motion may lead to unstable, exponentially growing modes [810].

For a long time, this counterintuitive causality-stability link of relativistic fluid dynamics was not well understood, even from a qualitative point of view. Gavassino’s work sheds light on this complicated problem and provides intuitive and surprisingly simple answers to the apparent paradoxes. Using concepts from relativity, he connects the causality of an arbitrary fluid-dynamical theory to its stability in any frame of reference.

The main result of this paper is the general proof that if a casual dissipative theory is stable in one frame of reference, it will also be stable in any other frame of reference. This conclusion considerably simplifies the task of analyzing the stability of dissipative fluid-dynamical theories. Prior to this work, for a theory of fluid dynamics to be consistent, its stability had to be proved in all possible reference frames—a cumbersome task that requires complicated and, often, numerical calculations. On the other hand, testing causality and stability of a fluid in a single frame is considerably simpler and can be accomplished analytically.

This paper also provides a simple and intuitive explanation for why different observers can disagree about the linear stability of a given dissipative theory and for why this only occurs if the corresponding theory violates causality. Gavassino constructs his answer by investigating whether different observers agree on whether a perturbation is growing or decaying in a fluid with respect to the observer’s own time (Fig. 1). He considers a perturbation that moves faster than light and whose energy is gradually dissipated—the perturbation amplitude decays over time from the perspective of a given observer. Since the perturbation is superluminal, it is traveling along a path that falls outside of the light cone—the region that describes how a flash of light spreads out through spacetime. The perturbation therefore links causally disconnected spacetime points that can be chronologically inverted in a relativistic frame transformation, that is, the part of this path that happens “earlier” and the part that happens “later” may be inverted depending on the observer’s frame of reference. The perturbation’s amplitude, which decays in the first observer’s frame, is then seen to increase from the point of view of another observer. Thus, the violation of causality can transform dissipative behavior into a growing instability simply by performing a reference-frame transformation.

This clever argument generally explains why dissipative theories that are not causal won’t ever provide a viable description of relativistic fluids, offering a simple test that any candidate for a theory of relativistic fluid dynamics must pass. A “correct” theory of relativistic fluid dynamics will be very different from its nonrelativistic counterparts. As new observations of astrophysical objects, including black holes and neutron star mergers, provide increasingly detailed and precise data, the need for a reliable relativistic-fluid-dynamical theory becomes more pressing. Most of these astrophysical processes are currently modeled using equations that do not include dissipation. Given the relevance of the topic for relativistic astrophysics as well as for heavy-ion collision simulations, Gavassino’s work will certainly rekindle interest in how best to understand the role of causality in hydrodynamics.

References

  1. L. Gavassino, “Can we make sense of dissipation without causality?” Phys. Rev. X 12, 041001 (2022).
  2. L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz, Fluid Mechanics: Volume 6, 2nd edition, edited by L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz (Butterworth-Heinemann, Oxford, 1987)[Amazon][WorldCat].
  3. G. S. Denicol et al., “Stability and causality in relativistic dissipative hydrodynamics,” J. Phys. G: Nucl. Part. Phys. 35, 115102 (2008).
  4. S. Pu et al., “Does stability of relativistic dissipative fluid dynamics imply causality?” Phys. Rev. D 81, 114039 (2010).
  5. W. A Hiscock and L. Lindblom, “Stability and causality in dissipative relativistic fluids,” Ann. Phys. 151, 466 (1983).
  6. W. Israel and J. M. Stewart, “Transient relativistic thermodynamics and kinetic theory,” Ann. Phys. 118, 341 (1979).
  7. I. Müller, “Speeds of propagation in classical and relativistic extended thermodynamics,” Living Rev. Relativ. 2 (1999).
  8. G. Denicol and D. H. Rischke, Microscopic Foundations of Relativistic Fluid Dynamics, Lecture Notes in Physics Vol. 990 (Springer, Cham, 2021)[Amazon][WorldCat].
  9. C. Eckart, “The thermodynamics of irreversible processes. III. Relativistic theory of the simple fluid,” Phys. Rev. 58, 919 (1940).
  10. W. A. Hiscock and L. Lindblom, “Generic instabilities in first-order dissipative relativistic fluid theories,” Phys. Rev. D 31, 725 (1985).

About the Author

Image of Gabriel Denicol

Gabriel Denicol received his Ph.D. in theoretical physics from Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany, in 2012. His thesis discussed how relativistic dissipative fluid dynamics emerges from microscopic theory, generalizing the famous and well-known Israel-Stewart theory. He was a postdoctoral fellow at McGill University, Canada, from 2012 to 2015, where he focused on the fluid-dynamical description of the hot and dense nuclear matter created in ultrarelativistic heavy-ion collisions. Afterward, he became a research assistant at Brookhaven National Laboratory, New York, where he stayed until 2016. In 2016, he joined the Department of Physics at Fluminense Federal University, Niterói, Brazil, as an adjunct professor. His current research fields include relativistic nonequilibrium phenomena, fluid dynamics, and transport theory.


Subject Areas

Fluid Dynamics

Related Articles

How Earth’s Magnetic Field Influences Flows in the Planet’s Core
Fluid Dynamics

How Earth’s Magnetic Field Influences Flows in the Planet’s Core

A “Little Earth Experiment” inside a giant magnet sheds light on so-far-unexplained flow patterns in Earth’s interior. Read More »

Predicting Droplet Size in Sprays
Fluid Dynamics

Predicting Droplet Size in Sprays

A new model of liquid sprays reveals the mechanisms behind droplet formation—providing important information for eventually controlling the droplet sizes in, for example, home cleaning sprays. Read More »

Tracking the Chaos That Surrounds the Aurora
Fluid Dynamics

Tracking the Chaos That Surrounds the Aurora

Applying data mining tools to a rich observational dataset has enabled researchers to track the turbulent plasma clouds that accompany the aurora. Read More »

More Articles